In a Times Op-Ed
piece entitled “God, Darwin and My College Biology Class” (NYT, 9/27/14), David
P. Barash, an evolutionary biologist and professor of psychology at the
University of Washington makes the following assertion: “The more we know of
evolution, the more unavoidable is the conclusion that living things, including
human beings, are produced by a natural, totally amoral process, with no
indication of a benevolent, controlling creator.” Adding benevolent to the mix
complicates the argument. Let’s make it simple. Does science explain everything?
For instance, Thomas Nagel, a professor of philosophy and law at NYU and an
avowed atheist has asked how naturalism “can account for the appearance, through the operation of the
laws of physics and chemistry, of conscious beings like ourselves, capable of
discovering those laws and understanding the universe that they govern.” (“A Philosopher Defends Religion,” The New
York Review of Books, 9/22/12). The philosopher John Searle has remarked
that free will and quanta are unanswered questions. Add to that the question of how
something could be created out of nothing, an old favorite on the
disenchantment talk circuit. Everyone wants certainty. Those who believe don’t
like it that science diminishes or extinguishes God’s role. Those who hone to a rationalist and analytic view of the world quote the last proposition of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, “Whereof one cannot speak,
thereof must one be silent.” But such certainties are neither spiritual nor
scientific. Hamlet’s famous line, “There are more things in heaven and earth, Horatio, Than are dreamt of in your philosophy” still points to the fact that
we may have to leave open items on our teleological agendas.
Showing posts with label Ludwig Wittgenstein. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Ludwig Wittgenstein. Show all posts
Friday, October 3, 2014
Tuesday, November 26, 2013
Leon Wieseltier’s Tractatus
Leon Wieseltier has written his own Tractatus. At least that’s the unequivocal aphoristic style in
which the first three paragraphs of his review of Ari Shavit’s My Promised Land: The Triumph and Tragedy of Israel in The New York Times Book Review (“The State of Israel,” NYT, 11/21/13) read like. Here are some of his propositions: 1) “Israel’s problems are too often combined and promoted
into a Problem, which has the effect of emptying the Jewish state of its
actuality and consigning it to a historical provisionality” 2) “existence itself must never be regarded as
an experiment” 3)“Israel is not a proposition…Its facticity is one of the
great accomplishments of the Jews’ history.” If we think back on Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus his proposition 1 was “The
world is all that is the case” and his last proposition number 7 reads,
“Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent.”With respect to his first
propostion, Wieseltier appears to be in complete agreement with Wittgenstein (the title of the review is incidentally a wonderful double-entendre). He creates a philosophical argument for a seemingly de facto state (unless one
discountenances political realities in favor of biblical justifications for the
piece of real estate we call Israel).Wieseltier, however, appears to be in disagreement
with proposition 7, the most quoted and compelling of Wittgenstein’s statements.
He is not silent about that which cannot be said. In fact, a lot of things
can’t be said about any political entity and particularly one as young as Israel. The creation of both the Roman
and Ottoman empires and modern nation states, like the birth and death of
individuals, remains one of the great mysteries of human existence and
something which great historians like Gibbon, Carlyle and Spengler have
spent lifetimes trying to understand.
Wednesday, July 4, 2012
Philosophy's Flights
![]() |
Photo of A.J. Ayer
In “Philosophy’s Flights” in last Sunday’s Review (NY Times,
7/1/12), Jim Holt asks “Is Philosophy Literature?” He’s talking about analytic
philosophers, philosophers of language like Bertrand Russell and later Thomas Nagel, Phlippa Foot (of trolley problem fame), Harvard’s Hilary
Putnam, Kwame Apiah, and Colin McGinn who all ultimately came to the fore as a reaction against the unverifiable propositions of metaphysics. Of course today there
are philosophers like Derek Parfit whose On What Matters attempts to bridge the gap between the limitations of the subjective (utilitarian) mind and broader ethical considerations. By the way, Holt’s piece is a selection from a
longer series called The Stone, which
can be found on the Times blog. Holt answers his own question with a
resounding yes but not before he makes the following qualification (in the
longer version) which is reminiscent of those commercials for new urine flow
medications on CNN that offer a list of disclaimers. “Today analytic philosophy
has a broader scope then it used to...it’s less obsessed with
dissecting languages; its more continuous with the sciences (this partly due to
the American philosopher Willard Quine who argued that language really has no
fixed system of meanings for philosophers to analyze). Yet whether they are
concerned with the nature of consciousness, of space-time or of the good life,
analytic philosophers continue to lay heavy stress on logical rigor in their
writings. The result, according to Martha Nussbaum (herself a sometime member
of the tribe), is a prevailing style that is ‘correct, scientific, abstract,
hygienically pallid’—a style meant to serve as ‘a kind of all-purpose
solvent.’” In this little passage Holt takes back what he giveth away and it’s
funny that missing from his list is the ne
plus ultra of all language philosophy A.J. Ayer’s wondrous Language, Truth and Logic which does for
analytic philosophy what Strunk and White’s The Elements of Style did for grammar. Still there are two exhibits that Holt offers in
defense of analytic philosophy as literature, Quine’s article “On What There
Is” which Holt comments “can be read over and over again, like a poem” and Saul
Kripke’s Naming and Necessity, a
compendium of three Princeton lectures which don’t contain “a dogmatic or pompous
word...and not a dull one either” that seem de
rigueur for anyone interested in his initial query. And then there are the first
and last lines of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus “The world is everything that is the
case” and “Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent.” Wasn’t
Wittgenstein the master of philosophical haiku?
|
Thursday, May 24, 2012
Dawkins vs God
We all know the great rivalries in boxing Louis and Schmeling, LaMotta and Robinson,Ali and Frazier, Ali and Foreman (which
culminated in the Rumble in the Jungle), Hagler and Hearns, Ward and Gatti. But
the realm of art and ideas also’s had its great bouts. Christopher Marlowe was
killed in a fight at the tender age of 29, though not by the rival Shakespeare. Popper vs. Wittgenstein gained notoriety for the poker. Llosa and Marquez came to blows over women and McCarthy vs Hellman was famous for Mary McCarthy’s quip about her opponent, “every
word she writes is a lie including 'and' and 'the.'" William Jennings Bryan
and Clarence Darrow paired off in the Scopes Trial or Monkey Trial, as it was known. Shakespeare wasn’t around to defend himself when Tolstoy said to Chekhov that
his plays were almost as bad as the bard’s. The recently deceased Carlos Fuentes got involved in a mud slinging contest with his old pal Octavio (Labyrinth of Solitude) Paz over politics
that went right on to Paz’s death in l998. Gore Vidal and William Buckley
similarly paired off over politics. Then of course there’s Jung and Freud whose
contest over the metaphysical was recently dramatized in A Dangerous Method. Perhaps the greatest intellectual rivalry of
all time is still drawing big crowds with Richard Dawkins coming close to
knocking out God.
Wednesday, March 7, 2012
Pina
Propostion 7, the last proposition of Wittgenstein’s Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus states, “Whereof one cannot speak, one must be silent.” One of the central themes of Wim Wenders' Pina is liminality. Pina Bausch's dance is liminal in that it deals with an edge of experience that can no longer be expressed in words. And what is that edge? It’s pain and love and longing. Her dancers describe Pina Bausch as a watcher. They were her paint and what a great way to view a film about a watcher but in 3-D (in several sequences of the film you actually watch an audience watching—in 3-D— which is one reason Pina could be subtitled adventures in perspective). And then there are the numerous set pieces which constitute the best of Pina, a woman being dismantled from a lover’s embrace, a man balancing sticks, a kind of Eve in reverse sequence where a muscular woman gives birth to a man. But from the point of view of meaning making one can’t help but ask if the edge is not an “event horizon,” followed by a black hole. Pina’s Bausch’s medium was dance/theater (her company was Tanztheater Wuppertal Pina Bausch) and one would assume that the element separating dance/theater from dance is the emphasis on human emotion over pure movement. Yet one wonders. If there are elements of human emotion that cannot be expressed in words, are they not sometimes best left to silence rather than movement?
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)